Skip to main content

comments: "On Substances and Causes Again" - Morphogenesis and Individuation, Chapter 1

[p. 7] Thus Individuation starts with a double critique: on the one hand of the Aristotelian hylomorphic dualism of matter and form, on the other of the monistic reduction of nature to a fundamental substance.

The critique of hylomophism is reviewed by Tim Ingold in Making, following Deleuze and Guattari, who were probably following Simondon, who I'm thinking was probably following Bergson.  The basic critique is that 'form' is not, in general, imprinted on matter in the way that a brick is shaped in a mold. For the record, Aristotlelian forms and Platonic forms are a bit different, but even so the co-emergence of form and matter is "modern" (say, Bergsonian) idea.  I'm less clear on the difference between Simondon and Bergson here.

But interesting to note that Simondon is firmly not a monist.  Given that some of our earliest posts here were written with The Monist in mind -- and that we continue to write with Pierce in mind -- it's worth rooting out the philosophical foundations.

[p. 9, fn 12] According to Simondon 'Nature' conceived as a macro-individual would be the silent and perfectly stable---dead---universe of maximum entropy; on the contrary, we are exclusively concerned with 'non-totalised' systems: 'Systems cannot be totalised, since the fact of considering them the sum of their elements spoils the awareness of what actually makes them systems: relative separation of the sets it contains, analogical structure, disparition in general, relational activity of information' (ILFI 234, n. 1).

This is reminiscent of the principles in Simondon's "Technical Mentality".  In a technical object, "The subsets are relatively detachable from the whole of which they are a part," -- but even so the technical object is not simply the sum of its parts.  According to the second principle, "If one wants to understand a being completely, one must study it by considering it in its entelechy, and not in its inactivity or its static state."  The technical object is understood (at least) through its 'disparition' and 'relational activity'.

[p. 14] at the psychical level 'we believe any thought, precisely as far as it is real, is a relation, i.e. it entails an historical aspect in its genesis' (ILFI 84)

This is a nice succinct summany of part of Simondon's "relational reductionism" i.e. not only are 'beings' to be understood in and through their relational activity, but so is 'understanding' itself.

[p. 15] Simondon's concepts, in fact, do not define any separate 'realms'---matter, living beings, psyche, society---traversed by individuals or any kind of substances of which individuals would be composed.  On the contrary, they indicate 'phases', processes, whose dynamic composition continuously constitutes and modifies the configuration of individuals, as it happens within a magnetic and gravitational field, in which different forces and processes constitute an irregular and unstable space, full of potentials, which can modify or be modified by whatever---matter or energy---becomes part of it.

I've come around to the view that the etymology of 'phase' is from the 'φάω'-associated root -- as distinct from the 'φατός'-associated root. Nevertheless, following Sloterdijk, we can conceptualise a basic "phatic architecture" (indicated in short2 by the sequence φάω/φαίνω/φατός) in which the 'phases' or 'appearances' of matter appear to a dynamic pre-individual field, in which relations are then formed.  Agamben has some good insights into the root meanings of 'dynamic' that I'd like to use to expand that aspect of the model (i.e., it's not just a throw-away term).

To make the picture here a bit more concrete, imagine light eminating from a star, or a campfire.  Although the light radiates out, well, radially, there are (at least potentially) a collection of trans-radially-directed vectors, that is, pointing along the various "rotational" directions around the imagined point source.  These vectors would correspond, for example, to the conversations that take place around the campfire, or to the time-binding relations (e.g. seasonal patterns, Mayan calendars, etc.) that take place as we rotate the sun.  If the figurative hypothesis is correct, then these "rotational" vectors create something that is indeed rather like a vortex (cf. Phatische Brief / short.pdf and Charles Wake), or to use a five-dollar word, a kind of 'autocatakinesthetic' entity -- namely the channel.  [BTW, I think "Wake" has a somewhat prophetic-seeming surname in this regard!]

[p. 20] If knowledge can trace back the lines which allow for the interpretation of the world according to stable laws, it is not because in the subject some a priori forms of sensibility exist, the consistence of which with raw data derived from sensation would be inexplicable; this happens because being as a subject and being as an object come from the same primitive reality, and thought, which now seems to institute an inexplicable relation between the object and the subject, in effect continues the initial individuation.

This is a somewhat convoluted sentence (yes, just one, -- count the capital letters!), but I think basically it is referring to is the "Trace" in the Nattiez/Molino picture of the semiotic situation.  Again keeping in mind the basic architecture (from Sloterdijk), the Trace is the "primitive reality"; we could position it at the "φαίνω" (phenomenal) level, whereas we would position the object at the "φάω" level and the subject at the "φατός" level.  This gives a proposal for generalising the basic phatic situation to other semiotic situations.

(I'd propose that phatic relationships -- even between e.g. humans and birds -- would give us something more fundamental than 'thought'.  I believe Jung says something similar in Psychology of the Unconscious.)

[p. 20] What Simondon calls the 'analogical method' is in fact the method of invention, an operation both theoretical and practical, which lacks any guarantees, as Simondon himself reveals when defining his own philosophy as 'a dramatic theory of the becoming of being' (Simondon 1960, p. 755).

This Analogical Method reminds me a bit of Koestler's "bisociation" which has been made much of in cognitive science -- although I think the Koestler strategy reads as though there are "stable laws" (see prev. quote).

[p. 21, fn 31]  'It is only abstractly that one can speak of an absolute indeterminism (realisable through a complete internal resonance) or an absolute determinism (realisable through a complete reciprocal independence of chronology and topology).  The general situation is a certain level of correlation between the chronology and topology of the system' (ILFI 148) ... 'Simondon's theory of individuation puts in relation the complexity of physical systems with morphogenetic processes' (Bontems 2010, p. 89).

Somewhat long-winded stuff; the second chapter in Morphogenesis and Individuation gets more into the question of indeterminism-vs-determinism, so more comments on that from me later.

[pp. 23-24] Simondon's philosophy of individuation entails a non-phenomenological 'split' between subject and object, which should be read against the backdrop of a different kind of separation.  He colocates the split not between the finite conscience and its infinite distance from the real, but rather between different levels of reality and knowledge. [...] Human beings in fact refer to different levels of reality which depend on correspondent levels of knowledge and practises.  It is as if living-man lived in-between different milieus without being able to make a synthesis of them.  Here it is what Canguilhem points to: 'a general theory of the milieu of the human being as technician and scientist ... remains to be elaborated. (Canguilhem 1952)

This business of being-in-between-milieus seems like something we could understand through a phatic lens.  I've often found myself interested by in-between states (e.g. walking from here to there, taking the bus, bus stations, etc.).  I remember speaking with a diagnosed-as-schizo-typical woman who hated the in-between state of doors in the process of being closed or opened.

The chapter describes how Canguilhem drawn on von Uexküll, whose trichotomy I think Rasmus has gone into elsewhere.  An interesting quote with respect to the idea of modern communication networks as sensing/affective networks is as follows:

[p. 25] The peculiarity of physical science as an instrument, is that it has allowed humans to include the shift between subjective milieus (Umwelt) and a geographical milieu (Umgebung) in a Welt which can---in line with principles---be adopted by the whole species to augment its predictive capacities.

The idea that aggegrated human attention can be better at predicting things than individual human attention has been evidenced with e.g. swarm intelligence (http://unu.ai/what-is-unu/ was on Reddit recently).  But other networks can do the same thing.

[p. 25] In short, what we call reality, which we know and live in, would be [...] the intertwining of different milieus, none of which can claim ontological primacy.  This unavoidable internal tension shifts the concept of 'geographical milieu'---against the mechanistic origin of the term milieu---to the original meaning of the concept, conceived in its relational meaning as what is 'between-two centres [entre-deux centres] (Canguilhem 1952, p. 130).

Nice; the French etymology is "mi-" (mid) 'lieu' (place).  So the very existence of a milieu is somehow channel-like.

[p. 27] Simondon ... programattically dismantles the 'conceptual couples' (form/matter, active/passive, subject/object, liberty/necessity) which have for centuries grounded a whole series of false alternatives, either opposing the individual to its milieu or dissolving it into the latter.

This quote nicely sums up how radical the Simondonian position is.  Also, the connection to the concept of 'milieux' and the way in which these are co-formed with individuals seems to secure Simondon's place in phatic studies (somewhere along the Jakobson-Elyachar line).

Reference:

Bardin, Andrea. "On substances and causes again: simondon’s philosophy of individuation and the critique of the metaphysical roots of determinism." Morphogenesis and individuation. Springer International Publishing, 2015. 3-31.


@incollection{bardin2015substances,
  title={On substances and causes again: simondon’s philosophy of individuation and the critique of the metaphysical roots of determinism},
  author={Bardin, Andrea},
  booktitle={Morphogenesis and individuation},
  pages={3--31},
  year={2015},
  publisher={Springer}
}




Of related interest


@article{bardin2013homme,
title={De l’homme {\`a} la mati{\`e}re: pour une “ontologie difficile”. Marx avec Simondon},
author={Bardin, Andrea},
journal={Cahiers Simondon},
volume={5},
pages={25--43},
year={2013}}
  
@book{simondon2010communication,

title={Communication et information: cours et conf{\'e}rences},
author={Simondon, Gilbert and Simondon, Nathalie and Chateau, Jean-Yves},
year={2010},
publisher={Transparence} } 

@book{canguilhem1992connaissance,
  title={La connaissance de la vie},
  author={Canguilhem, Georges},
  year={1992},
  publisher={Vrin}
}



Comments

  1. I found four pages about von Uexküll on Jesus-Walked...:

    http://jeesusjalutasallveelaeval.blogspot.co.uk/2013/01/ecosemiotic-readings.html
    http://jeesusjalutasallveelaeval.blogspot.co.uk/2013/06/biosemiotics-semiotic-web-1991.html
    http://jeesusjalutasallveelaeval.blogspot.co.uk/2011/11/onto-ethologies.html
    http://jeesusjalutasallveelaeval.blogspot.co.uk/2014/05/umwelt-and-animal-communication.html

    I think he's also mentioned in the 6x9 note? Is that everything?

    I'd like to add a new subsection or sub-subsection that makes connections back from the theorists like Simondon and Sloterdijk to the fundamental researchers. I was thinking that v. Uexküll might be a "missing link" but haven't had a chance to investigate properly. Are there other relevant figures? It may be hard to tell w/o reading Simondon and Canguilhem's primary texts...

    ReplyDelete
  2. One more appeared very recently -- maybe while I was writing the above?

    http://jeesusjalutasallveelaeval.blogspot.co.uk/2016/09/social-attitudes-and-nonsymbolic.html

    ReplyDelete

Post a Comment

Popular posts from this blog

The plot thickens (with Herbert Spencer)

In a paper attempting to outline the conceptual domain of comparative psychology , Herbert Spencer discusses the quality of impulsiveness in relation with human races (bearded and unbearded). Among his "sundry questions of interests" about the relationship between mental energy, evolution, complexity, etc. are the following notes: ( b ) What connection is there between this trait and the social state? Clearly a very explosive nature - such as that of the Bushman - is unfit for social; and, commonly, social union, when by any means established, checks impulsiveness. ( c ) What respective shares in checking impulsiveness are taken by the feelings which the social state fosters - such as the fear of surrounding individuals, the instinct of sociality , the desire to accumulate property, the sympathetic feelings , the sentiment of justice? These, which require a social environment for their development, all of them involve imaginations of consequences more or less distant; and th

Vitruvius Pollio, The origin of the dwelling house

 Chapter 1 of Book II of "Ten Books on Architecture", available from Project Gutenberg .  Sections 1, 2, and 7 (from the Richard Schofield translation published by Penguin rather than the one here) are quoted on pp. 218-219 of Spheres II by Peter Sloterdijk.  Pay particular attention to Section 2. 1. The men of old were born like the wild beasts, in woods, caves, and groves, and lived on savage fare. As time went on, the thickly crowded trees in a certain place, tossed by storms and winds, and rubbing their branches against one another, caught fire, and so the inhabitants of the place were put to flight, being terrified by the furious flame. After it subsided, they drew near, and observing that they were very comfortable standing before the warm fire, they put on logs and, while thus keeping it alive, brought up other people to it, showing them by signs how much comfort they got from it. In that gathering of men, at a time when utterance of sound was purely individual, fro